Last week I described how Robert Frank wants to discourage “conspicuous consumption” via big houses, cars, and barbecues, because he thinks they cause large positional (i.e., relative status) harms on others. After describing our best data on positionality, I asked if Frank would endorse its implication that we tax should beauty aids, education, and sports.
Both Robert Frank and Geoffrey Miller eagerly point out when data shows folks being less happy doing what Frank and Miller dislike, but this doesn’t obviously fit their big theories: it is not obvious why activities that produce positional side effects (Frank), or activities that are inefficient signals (Miller), should make us less happy.
There is a very different argument one could offer however, even if neither Frank nor Miller offer it directly. One could argue that we should in general tax the activities that make people less happy. To justify this we’d have to assume that humans tend for some reason to do too little of what makes them happy, but it doesn’t require that we know exactly what that reason is.
Below is Table 6.1, from a 2008 paper on the “net affect” of 45 ways we spent our time. (Net affect combines six emotions felt during the activity: happy, tired, stress, sad, interested, and pain.) A simple policy of taxing low affect activities and subsidizing the others would have us subsidize not just parties, doing and spectating sports, exercise, playing with kids, walking dogs, and music, but also subsidize religion, eating out, and shopping. We would tax not just work, commuting, home maintenance, and most housework, but also tax school and homework, writing by hand, buying medical services, doing personal medical care, and caring for adults.
If you don’t endorse these policies, you must have other policy criteria than just encouraging activities that directly make us happy. That table:
As that paper concludes:
The method of [National Time Accounting] does not lead to immediate policy recommendations. For example, the fact that spending time socializing may be more enjoyable than working for pay for the average person does not necessarily lead to the recommendation that people should socialize more and work less. Paid work is obviously required to afford a certain life style.
at least if we believe people are biased against happiness.
We do know that people are very bad at recollecting past experience and at forecasting future experience. Rather than a tax on unhappiness, however, I would favor a subsidy on hedonimeters (see Kahneman and Rees, p. 292). People could in principle overcome these affective biases if they could precisely measure and record how happy they are.
Robin,
I like where you are going with this, but these data are a bad place to start for trying to figure out what makes us happy and what doesn't. Work, for example, provided it is matched to our ability, can supposedly make us very happy, and fulfilled. Long commutes and big houses make us slightly LESS happy than short commutes and small houses - hence in this instance the consumption tax would be efficient for maximum happiness.
This might be a good place to start:
http://www.happinesshypothe...